Law and Disagreement

Law and Disagreement

Jeremy Waldron

Language: English

Pages: 344

ISBN: 0199243034

Format: PDF / Kindle (mobi) / ePub


When people disagree about justice and about individual rights, how should political decisions be made among them? How should they decide about issues like tax policy, welfare provision, criminal procedure, discrimination law, hate speech, pornography, political dissent and the limits of religious toleration?

The most familiar answer is that these decisions should be made democratically, by majority voting among the people or their representatives. Often, however, this answer is qualified by adding ' providing that the majority decision does not violate individual rights.'

In this book Jeremy Waldron has revisited and thoroughly revised thirteen of his most recent essays. He argues that the familiar answer is correct, but that the qualification about individual rights is incoherent. If rights are the very things we disagree about, then we are quarrelling precisely about what that qualification should amount to. At best, what it means is that disagreements about rights should be resolved by some other procedure, for example, by majority voting, not among the people or their representatives, but among judges in a court. This proposal - although initially attractive - seems much less agreeable when we consider that the judges too disagree about rights, and they disagree about them along exactly the same lines as the citizens.

This book offers a comprehensive critique of the idea of the judicial review of legislation. The author argues that a belief in rights is not the same as a commitment to a Bill of Rights. He shows the flaws and difficulties in many common defenses of the 'democratic' character of judicial review. And he argues for an alternative approach to the problem of disagreement: when disagreements about rights arise, the respectful way to resolve them is by decision-making among the right-holders on a basis that reflects an equal respect for them as the holders of views about rights. This respect for ordinary right-holders, he argues, has been sadly lacking in the theories of justice, rights, and constitutionalism put forward in recent years by philosophers such as John Rawls and Donald Dworkin.

But the book is not only about judicial review. The first tranche of essays is devoted to a theory of legislation, a theory which highlights the size, the scale and the diversity of modern legislative assemblies. Although legislation is often denigrated as a source of law, Waldron seeks to restore its tattered dignity. He deprecates the tendency to disparage legislatures and argues that such disparagement is often a way of bolstering the legitimacy of the courts, as if we had to transform our parliaments into something like the American Congress to justify importing American-style judicial reviews.

Law and Disagreement redresses the balances in modern jurisprudence. It presents legislation by a representative assembly as a form of law making which is especially apt for a society whose members disagree with one another about fundamental issues of principle, for it is a form of law making that does not attempt to conceal the fact that our decisions are made and claim their authority in the midst of, not in spite of, our political and moral disagreements.

This timely rights-based defense of majoritarian legislation will be welcomed by scholars of legal and political philosophy throughout the world.

Democratic Enlightenment: Philosophy, Revolution, and Human Rights 1750-1790

Vita activa: La condizione umana

Common Sense: and The American Crisis I (Penguin Classics)

Hume: A Very Short Introduction (Very Short Introductions)

Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books II-IV

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

constrains in the future? It seems to me that the existence of good faith disagreement about the content of the precommitment at the time that it is proposed is always a reason for answering that question in the affirmative. Disagreement ex ante portends unreasonableness ex post. So although the inter-generational dimension is not necessarily conclusive against the precommitment characterization of constitutional constraints, it is likely to be conclusive in fact inasmuch as the future has a

well-ordered by the principles of justice for which I have argued.’ John Rawls does something like this for his theory, explicating familiar rule-of-law precepts as desiderata for procedural justice and institutional design, and connecting the idea of legality with liberal principles of publicity, generality, and transparency.14 But this sort of approach to general jurisprudence is too easy. Of course there is less of a problem for legal obligation and the rule of law in a society whose citizens

purposes of the Raz/Marmor argument, these men would not even have understood, let alone have had a better grasp than us of, the conditions for the subsistence of a continental superpower as a free and constitutional republic, under conditions of ethnic diversity, democratic equality, and post-industrial crisis. There may be a case for regarding the text of the Constitution as a stable and indispensable framework to house the volatility and vicissitudes of modern politics.13 But that stabilizing

by Ronald Dworkin’s theory of rights as ‘trumps’.21 If we say that it is the function of rights to ‘trump’ majority-decisions, it is surely incumbent on us to add some acknowledgement that people disagree about what rights we have and to offer some basis whereby that disagreement might be resolved, so that there is something determinate to do the trumping. We cannot play trumps if we disagree about the suits. Or if we do, we are open to what I regard as the unanswerable cynicism of Thomas Hobbes

contrary: they threaten to reproduce the very conflict about justice with which we began. An example of such a principle is the following, which I shall call Modified Majoritarianism: ‘Let the majority prevail except in cases where the majority decision threatens individual rights.’ If people disagree (as we know they do) about what rights we have or about what threatens them, this principle will be hopeless. Suppose, in the example given above, that many members of the minority believe single

Download sample

Download